Reading 2.5 – What if we had no verbal behavior?

Chapter 2 – It’s Just Verbal Behavior

Reading 2.5 – What if we had no verbal behavior?

The predominant challenge facing students of behavior analysis, not to mention those well into their careers, is dealing with the insidious and pervasive contributions of mentalism to colloquial and even professional dialects. If you are not utterly convinced of this proposition, you should take a careful look at Reading 3.3 titled, “How good are you at recognizing mentalism?”

With that essay as required background, let us consider an interesting way to address the challenges of mentalism – imagining that we have no verbal repertoire. This is a more difficult exercise than you might suspect. Although we’ve all been there as babies and early toddlers, we weren’t aware of much at that age (see Reading 6.5). After these first few years, however, our verbal communities gifted us with a growing verbal repertoire. We have enjoyed the capability of talking and listening in one form or another ever since, the only exceptions taking the form of substantial limitations in brain function.

The voice in our head

Reading 4.1 (“The mind’s eye and the voice in our head”) discusses the lack of a verbal repertoire by considering what it would be like to not be able to think. The conventional conception of thinking is that it is largely a verbal exercise. Taking away that option means that we would interact with our environment without awareness, recognition, or reflection. After all, being aware of our experiences means being able to identify, label, or describe them – all verbal responses. Although it might seem hard to imagine what this would be like, we often behave without being aware of what we are doing. I’ve often used the example of driving while being distracted, such as while daydreaming. During these hopefully brief interludes, we are entirely oblivious to what we are doing that keeps us from having a horrible accident. Meanwhile, we are responding by modulating the steering wheel, accelerator, and brakes as required by the highway environment, only later realizing that we have no idea of what we’ve been seeing and doing for the past few minutes.

In other words, without the verbal repertoire that is the foundation for awareness, we simply respond as the current environment and our learning history dictate. Another way of putting it is that without a verbal repertoire, we respond to our environment just as other animals do. Unfortunately, our understanding of the behavior of other species, especially those we’re around all the time such as the family dog, is contaminated by our tendency to assume that they too have an active mental life that plays a significant role in their behavior. Lacking any other way of describing of explaining their behavior, we fail to appreciate the example they provide of how life is lived without awareness.

Only a side effect

It may seem unhelpful to the theme of this reading to point out that the lack of a verbal repertoire greatly reduces the temptation to propose mental causes for behavior, but that is actually getting to the point. The verbal community teaches us to attribute a powerful and pervasive causality to our verbal repertoire. Without exploring alternative possibilities, we assume that our verbal behavior is a primary source of control over the behavior of others, as well as over our own behavior. Extending that assumed influence to our private verbal behavior greatly multiplies the opportunities for causal mischief.

Guided by colloquial dialect, it is easy to buy into ways this verbal repertoire might supplement – if not dominate – environmental causes underlying our behavior. The assumed mechanism for that role lies in mental processes of some sort, which are typically offered as the most important explanations for behavior. If these processes seem not merely familiar but patently obvious, remember that we’ve heard little else all our lives. Absent training in behavior analysis, it’s understandable that we would suppose that the impact of environmental consequences, which we’ve not been taught to notice or appreciate, is surpassed by the ability of mental processes to manage their effects.

Behavior analysts know that our verbal repertoire is fully learned. In contrast, our cultural training is inconsistent on this point, although it is at least clear in assigning verbal behavior a key role in our mental life. However, this mental domain is entirely the creation of our everyday verbal repertoire. Without this repertoire, there would be no basis for attributing so much of our behavior to mental processes. In fact, that mental domain is not a distinct physical phenomenon, in spite of attempts to redefine it in terms of neurological activity in the brain. It is not available to other species and neither is it a meaningful concept for those humans who for whatever reason have not learned a verbal repertoire. The assumed existence and utility of mentalism in any form depends entirely on having learned to talk. Mentalism is only a side effect of that training history and a misleading distraction at that.

References

Reading 3.3 – How good are you at recognizing mentalism?
Reading 4.1 – The mind’s eye and the voice in our head.
Reading 6.5 – What is remembering and why don’t we remember when we were toddlers?